Tuesday, April 23, 2019
Can A Board's Knowing Violation of the Law Also Be Entirely Fair? How About Moral?
Prof. Justin Pace, Haworth College of Business, Western Michigan University recently sent me his paper, Rogue Corporations: Unlawful Corporate Conduct and Fiduciary Duty. In it, he discusses Delaware's "per se doctrine where the board directs the corporation to violate the law. A knowing violation of positive law is bad faith, which falls under the duty of loyalty. The business judgment rule will not apply and exculpation will not be available under Section 102(b)(7). The shareholders may not even need to show harm."
In the paper, he considers this concept from a moral and ethical perspective, which are interesting in their own right, though I remain more interested in the doctrine itself. The paper is worth a look. A few comments of my own, after the abstract:
Abstract
On February 28, 2018, Dick’s Sporting Goods announced that it would no longer sell long guns to 18- to 20-year-olds. On March 8, 2018, Dick’s was sued for violating the Michigan Elliott-Larsen Civil Rights Act, which prohibits discrimination on the basis of age in public accommodations. Dick’s and Walmart were also sued for violating Oregon’s ban on age discrimination. In addition to corporate liability under various state civil rights acts, directors of Dick’s and Walmart face the threat of suit for breaching their fiduciary duties—suits that may be much harder to defend than the more usual breach of fiduciary duty suit.
Delaware corporation law appears to have an underappreciated per se doctrine where the board directs the corporation to violate the law. A knowing violation of positive law is bad faith, which falls under the duty of loyalty. The business judgment rule will not apply and exculpation will not be available under Section 102(b)(7). The shareholders may not even need to show harm.
This paper examines the relevant legal doctrine but also takes a step back to consider what the rule should be from an ethical and a moral standpoint. To do so, rather than apply traditional corporate governance arguments, this paper considers broader moral theories. In addition to the utilitarian calculus that is so ubiquitous in corporate governance scholarship via the law and economics movement, this paper considers the liberalism of both John Rawls and Robert Nozick. But liberalism may seem less persuasive given the rise of illiberalism politically on both the American right and left. Given that, this paper also considers two non-liberal models: one a populist modification of Charles Taylor’s democratic communitarianism and the other Catholic Social Thought.
Unsurprisingly, the proper rule depends on which moral theory is applied. If that theory is liberalism (of either form covered), then a per se approach is troubling. Harm to the corporation must be shown, and either the Delaware legislature or the corporate players, depending on the form of liberalism, must acquiesce to a per se rule. Counterintuitively, it is the per se rule that runs counter to basic democratic norms. It gives the power to litigate in response to harm not to the party harmed but to a third party. Given the divergent results from applying different moral theories, and given the democratic difficulty, the Delaware legislature should clarify the standard. It will likely find that a harsh, per se standard is unjustified.
First, I have always thought that some people read DGCL § 102(b)(7) too literally (or at least broadly). The statute reads:
(b) In addition to the matters required to be set forth in the certificate of incorporation by subsection (a) of this section, the certificate of incorporation may also contain any or all of the following matters:
. . . .
(7) A provision eliminating or limiting the personal liability of a director to the corporation or its stockholders for monetary damages for breach of fiduciary duty as a director, provided that such provision shall not eliminate or limit the liability of a director: (i) For any breach of the director's duty of loyalty to the corporation or its stockholders; (ii) for acts or omissions not in good faith or which involve intentional misconduct or a knowing violation of law; (iii) under § 174 of this title; or (iv) for any transaction from which the director derived an improper personal benefit. No such provision shall eliminate or limit the liability of a director for any act or omission occurring prior to the date when such provision becomes effective. All references in this paragraph to a director shall also be deemed to refer to such other person or persons, if any, who, pursuant to a provision of the certificate of incorporation in accordance with § 141(a)of this title, exercise or perform any of the powers or duties otherwise conferred or imposed upon the board of directors by this title.
I have never been one to believe that directors face potential liability for any type of "knowing violation of law." Anyone who has seen a UPS or FedEx truck in New York City knows that the drivers knowingly park illegally and risk tickets (which they often get) for doing the job. It is a cost of doing business, and I find it hard to believe any court would hold directors liable for such a thing, though directors certainly know (or should) of the practice. That would make for one of the most absurd Caremark-like cases ever, in my view.
Prof. Pace argues in his paper:
A per se standard might prove lucrative. It opens up liability for losses normally insulated by business judgment rule. If Nike loses market share because it made Colin Kaepernick the face of a large marketing campaign, shareholders cannot successfully sue because that decision is protected by the business judgment rule. But if Dick’s Sporting Goods loses market share because it stops selling long guns to 18- to 20-year-olds, shareholders presumably can sue and recover based on that market share, even though civil liability for violating state bars on age discrimination may be negligible.
Perhaps, but I would still think that most courts would likely work around this. First, I think a court could easily calculate damages as the modest civil liability incurred, not the lost market share. Second, in Dick's Sporting Goods situation, as I observed elsewhere, "it is worth noting that Dick's sales dropped, but profits rose after the decision because the company cut costs by replacing some guns with higher-margin items." If there is no harm, is there a foul? Or maybe better said, it is possible that there is no director liability unless one can show actual harm.
I will concede that DGCL § 102(b)(7) likely eliminates business judgment rule protection for directors where one can show a knowing violation of the law. However, getting past the business judgment rule does not automatically lead to liability. It simply allows the court to review the board's decision, but the plaintiff still must show harm. And I am not at all sure one can show harm in the Dick's gun sales circumstance. It is, in my view, entirely fair. I also gather that I am may be in the minority on this one. But a good conversation, either way.
https://lawprofessors.typepad.com/business_law/2019/04/can-a-boards-knowing-violation-of-the-law-also-be-entirely-fair-how-about-moral-.html
Comments
Is it clear that your UPS truck example shows a knowing violation of law by the directors? It's true, directors know that their employees are sometimes violating the law. But they do not know about the specific individual instances, they just know that some violations will occur. And crucially, it is not the directors themselves violating the law. Caremark doesn't require a perfect compliance system, not even anything remotely close to perfection. In an imperfect system, it is predictable that the system will fail to stop some employees from breaking some laws, and indeed it will sometimes be predictable what laws are being violated with some regularity. But as I read Caremark, that's no problem, given the impossibility of a perfect compliance system, so long as the directors themselves are not deliberately violating the law.
Posted by: Brett McDonnell | Apr 24, 2019 7:13:08 AM
Thanks for the comment, Brett. Caremark doesn't require perfect compliance, but it does require some level of response once one is on notice (kind of the old torts rule of a dog gets one bite). The fact that UPS drivers get tickets would not be an inherent violation of directors' duties but under the reading Prof. Pace provides for 102(b)(7), I do think it would be problematic to have getting regular parking tickets to be part of the delivery plan. That is, if there is no penalty to drivers or procedure manual that tells them they must park legally, it would seem the board is condoning deliberate lawbreaking. Caremark is an almost impossible liability threshold to meet, anyway, but I think the Caremark duty is broader than knowing exactly who is doing the lawbreaking. With regard to UPS and FedEx, I do think it is pervasive enough that directors would know its happening. The fact that directors don't appear worried about it, I think, does add further support for the idea that (despite the language of 102(b)(7)) it's not a big concern.
Posted by: Joshua Fershee | Apr 24, 2019 9:56:21 AM
Thank you for your thoughtful remarks.
A couple notes on the practical side of things:
Chief Justice Strine has made it pretty clear that he does take a strict view. But it is by no means clear that the Chancery Court or the other justices would agree.
The Delaware courts have whittled away at damages for fiduciary litigation in any number of ways, but they haven't been willing to disclaim the traditional, equitable approach.
It isn't clear what exactly the Delaware courts would do if they face the issue squarely, but that uncertainty is enough that I think it ought to be considered a significant risk for a company like Uber or Dick's (if not for most companies).
Posted by: H. Justin Pace | Apr 23, 2019 2:02:49 PM